rthur Koestler, an iconoclastic thinker
who could always be counted on for a catchy title, called his
history of cosmology "The Sleepwalkers." The way mankind lurched and
stumbled toward the truth reminded him "more of a sleepwalker's
performance than an electronic brain's."
Obsessions and fixations were as common as brilliant chains of
reasoning, and every step forward seemed to be countered by two
steps sideways and a half step back.
The most erratic of the somnambulists on this zigzag trail was
the man often called the father of modern science, Galileo. Far from
being the selfless hero of popular legend who championed scientific
truth over blind religious faith, he comes off in Koestler's book,
published in 1959, as a vainglorious self-promoter spoiling for a
fight.
The primary reason he was hauled before the Inquisition, Koestler
argued, was not for teaching Copernicus's view that Earth and the
planets revolved around the Sun, but for offending so many of his
sympathizers — and, most important, for insisting that Copernicanism
was not just a theory, but an indisputable truth.
Pushing this idea further, two new books, "Galileo's Mistake," by
Wade Rowland (Arcade Publishing), and "Galileo in Rome" by William
R. Shea and Mariano Artigas (Oxford University Press), almost seem
to sympathize with the inquisitors, making Galileo look like the
dogmatist.
That may be going overboard, but contrarian views have the virtue
of jarring the brain from its slumber and forcing one to consider an
old story in a new way. The trial of Galileo is usually cast as a
black-and-white battle between faith and reason. But something far
more interesting may have been at stake: a fight over the very
nature of what is meant by a scientific theory.
Even Galileo's detractors concede his brilliance as a scientist.
His work on mechanics, the motion of pendulums and of balls rolling
down inclined planes, helped open the way for the modern view of a
universe that operates not by godly caprice, but according to
discernible mathematical laws.
By showing with his telescope that Jupiter had moons, he
demonstrated that not everything revolved around the Earth. By
showing that Venus had moonlike phases, he made a strong case that
at least this one planet traveled around the Sun.
Neither discovery, however, proved that Copernicus was right. The
data could also be explained by a rival theory, championed by Tycho
Brahe — a masterpiece of compromise in which Mercury, Venus, Mars,
Jupiter and Saturn revolve around the Sun and the whole whirling
assemblage orbits Earth.
When science alone was not enough to sustain an argument, Galileo
pulled out the polemics. He was that rarity among physicists, one
who could write in a clear, persuasive and entertaining way. His
"Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems," in which three
noblemen, Salviati, Sagredo and Simplicio, meet in Venice to argue
over the relative merits of Ptolemy's ancient Earth-centered cosmos
and the newer Sun-centered Copernicanism, may be the first great
piece of popular science writing.
The book was also his downfall. It was Galileo the writer, not
Galileo the scientist, who got himself into trouble. Like so many
people who are good with words, he succumbed to the temptation of
making his opponents seem not just wrong, but also stupid.
In the dialogue, it is the naïve apologist for Ptolemaic
astronomy who is given the belittling name Simplicio, and from his
mouth comes the very argument against Copernicanism made by the one
man Galileo could not afford to offend, Pope Urban VIII.
No matter how well a theory seems to account for the phenomena,
Simplicio argues, it may still be illusory. A God of infinite
ability may have made a universe far too subtle and complex to be
fathomed by feeble human minds.
Like many of Galileo's sympathizers, Urban felt that he had been
mocked. A friend and supporter was turned into an enemy.
But this was far more than a personal squabble. The authors of
"Galileo in Rome" say his most damaging offense was overstating his
case, contending that he had proved Copernicus to be right and
Ptolemy to be wrong. (With a slightly different thrust, Mr. Rowland
argues that Galileo's mistake was insisting on science as the only
means of obtaining truth.)
There is something to the argument. Though Galileo had been
admonished not to advocate Copernicanism, Urban had no objection to
his presenting it as a hypothesis, one of several possible
explanations for celestial motion. Taking a similar tack, biblical
creationists call for the story of Genesis to be taught side by side
with evolutionary biology.
To the Roman church, the systems of Ptolemy and Copernicus were
just models, ways for mortals to predict astronomical events.
Ptolemy could accurately account for the movements of the planets,
if one pretended that they traveled not just in circles, but in
circles within circles around a stationary Earth.
Add enough of these "epicycles" and the predictions could be
honed as precisely as you liked. No one probably believed that the
planets really careened like a loop-the-loop carnival ride. The
Ptolemaic system was intended as a device for making calculations,
not as a picture of the universe.
In other words, the map is not the territory — an argument with a
very modern ring. Centuries after Galileo's book was banned, the
physicist J. M. Jauch resurrected Salviati, Sagredo and Simplicio to
discuss whether a new theory called quantum mechanics provided a
true picture of an underlying reality or was just a convenient
mathematical tool. He called his book "Are Quanta Real? A Galilean
Dialogue" (Indiana University Press, 1973).
Faced with conflicting theories that both account for the facts,
scientists lean toward the one that is the more elegant and
economical. But here, Koestler showed, Galileo was on thin ice. To
preserve the illusion that the planets move in perfect circles,
Copernicus also had to resort to a convoluted arrangement of
epicycles.
It was Galileo's contemporary, Kepler, who made the crucial
breakthrough, replacing the circles with ellipses and dispensing
with the Ptolemaic curlicues. Galileo, obsessed as any ancient with
what Koestler called the "circular dogma," would barely give Kepler
the time of day. He also dismissed Kepler's notion that the tides
were caused by the pull of the Moon as mere astrological
superstition. The rhythmic sloshing, Galileo wrongly insisted, was a
natural result of the combined motions of Earth's daily revolution
and its orbit around the Sun. He considered that to be the real
clincher to the Copernican argument, proof that Earth did not stand
still.
For all his virtues, Galileo, mind firmly shut, was using an
incorrect argument to promote a cosmology that has turned out to be
wrong. The folly of the inquisitors was treating this bullheaded
fumbling — the essence of the scientific search — as a
crime.